Friday, November 2, 2012

Inherit the Wind: An Aristotelian Tragedy?



Aristotle, in his Poetics, famously defined tragedy as follows:

A tragedy, then, is the imitation of an action that is serious and also, as having magnitude, complete in itself; in language with pleasurable accessories, each kind brought in separately in the parts of the work; in a dramatic, not in a narrative form; with incidents arousing pity and fear, wherewith to accomplish its catharsis of such emotions. (translation by Imgram Bywater: 35).1

While there is no universal agreement that Aristotle’s definition is the only or even the best definition of tragedy, it does serve as a springboard for any discussion of the tragic art.  Why is generic definition important?  First, it provides the prospective reader with a set of expectations about a work.  Second, it provides critics a set of criteria by which they can evaluate the quality of the work. Finally, because it assigns qualitative value to a works:  tragedy for example is considered more important than romantic comedy.


First, according to Aristotle, a tragedy is an “imitation of an action that is serious.”   Hamilton W. Fyfe, I think, correctly defines the “imitation” as a “recreation of life” while O. B. Hardison, adds that, “if they are well done, [tragedy] reveal(s) generic qualities—the presence of the universal in the particular.”2 3 What Hardison means is that the imitated action has relevance to a general public, that the events, even if they are fantastical, can be imagined as relatable to the proverbial everyman.  Take for example, Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex.  Few of us will ever be a king and even fewer will murder our father and marry our mother, but most of us will occasionally undertake journeys of self-discovery which reveal unpleasant and unexpected aspects of our personalities.  And because we have experienced similar journeys though of a smaller magnitude we are able to emphasize with Oedipus and, hopefully learn from his suffering.  The “action” being imitated is, however, really less than a true “recreation of life” because the actions portrayed are selected to advance a particular story line and purpose.  Time is by necessity compressed.  When Oedipus sends for Tiresias, the blind prophet shows up immediately, as if he was waiting just around the corner.  We don’t see Oedipus taking a bathroom breaks because it is not relevant to the purpose of the action being imitated.  From all the events and actions that would naturally take place over the course of Oedipus’ investigation, Sophocles only selects those particular actions that advance the purpose of the story he wants to tell and leads the audience to the generalization he wishes to make, i.e.,

             From hence the lesson draw,-
             To reckon no man happy till ye see-
             The closing day; until he pass the bourn-
Which severs life from death, unscathed by woe.

The action need not be historically accurate or even an actual event, but something that may have happened, conforming to the laws of probably and necessity.  The action must be unified and complete, meaning it must present the actions in a logical sequence with a clear beginning, middle and end; and incidents and actions must logically arise from that which has gone before.  Unlike the epic or the history, tragedy is not designed to describe or explain what happened, but instead is intended to evoke an emotional response.  Unlike comedy, the other dramatic form explored by Aristotle, which is intended to generate mirth, tragedy has a more serious purpose: to arouse pity and fear in its audience. 

Tragedy’s ability to arouse fear and pity then purge these emotions from the audience is probably tragedy’s most distinctive feature.  We fear for Oedipus because we can see where the action is going even if he can’t and we pity him when all is finally revealed, resulting in his destruction.  But does the end of Oedipus Rex result in a catharsis of the fear and pity the tragedy provokes?  In what ways might catharsis be achieved?  Aristotle does not explain, but subsequent critics have debated both what catharsis means and how it is accomplished.  In general, the majority opinion is that a successful tragedy will provide the audience a sense of relief that helps them handle daily living in calmer fashion.  In contemporary popular culture, the purging of emotion by tragedy is akin to the theory that viewing violent films allow the viewer to exorcise violent impulse by vicariously expending these impulses by identification with the theatrical perpetrator of violence.  This theory is of course highly controversial, but if it were true it would provide a suitable parallel to Aristotle’s theory of catharsis.

Tragedy may accomplish catharsis in a number of ways.  One that comes to mind is the tragedy of the martyr, the man who suffers for his beliefs and is ennobled by his courage in the face of torment and death.  We fear for and pity William Wallace in Mel Gibson’s 1995 Academy Award winning film Braveheart, but we are so inspired by his courage in the face of a torturous death and the subsequent triumph of his cause, that we leave the theater, not shuddering from fear or sobbing from pity, but uplifted by his example.  It might also be suggested that catharsis can be achieved by the relief that no matter how bad things might seem, they are better than they were for the tragic protagonist.  We might for example have problems with our children, but for few of us will have things as bad as those experienced by King Lear.  We fear for and pity Lear, but there may be a profound sense of relief in the fact that they are happening to him and not to us.  Another theory of catharsis suggests that an individual can learn to modulate their emotional responses to life events by identifying with and learning from the suffering protagonist.  For example when watching the protagonist confront the death of a child, the audience member may be better prepared to handle a real life tragedy by having vicariously participating in a similar event before an actual tragedy occurs in their own life.  Finally, catharsis might be achieved by simply overloading the emotions to such an extent that the audience “short circuits,” that is they have nothing emotionally left to give.  A play like Romeo and Juliet might achieve this effect.  By the end of the play, the audience may be “cried out” so to speak.  They are numbed by the tragic events and drained of the ability to further respond emotionally.

With all this being said, can we classify Inherit the Wind as an Aristotelian tragedy?  I believe that we can.  I would suggest that Inherit the Wind  has as its’ tragic protagonist  Matthew Harrison Brady.  The play, as we have seen in the previous essay, is the imitation of an action that is serious:  the struggle between science and faith, some would say between reason and superstition.  One side wishes to push against the barriers to knowledge and the other wishes to make the barriers more formidable.  One side wants to move forward regardless of consequences and the other wishes to mark time, believing that things as they are “are good enough for me.”

I again return to Aristotle’s Poetics for th definition of a tragic protagonist.  Aristotle suggests that the actions of the hero of a tragedy must evoke in the audience a sense of pity or fear. The pity arises when a person receives undeserved misfortune and the fear comes when the misfortune befalls a man like us.  Like us, he is man “who is not eminently good and just, yet whose misfortune is brought about not by vice or depravity, but by some error or frailty,” either some weakness of character or some moral blindness.  Unlike most of us, the tragic protagonist should be one “who is highly renowned and prosperous” which adds to the seriousness of the action.

Matthew Harrison Brady is the champion of the status quo.  He is renowned as a three time Populist contender for the presidency and an enthusiastic supporter of Bible literalism.  He devoutly believes that Darwinism is an inherent threat to man’s morality, an insult to man’s dignity and a frontal attack on religion.   He tells the reporters covering the case “that here in Hillsboro we are fighting the fight of the Faithful throughout the world!” While his oration is grandiose, his feelings are sincere,  In a quiet discussion with Drummond, he shows his Populist roots by defending the faithful, saying:

These are simple people, Henry. Poor people. They work hard and they need to believe in something… something beautiful. They’re seeking for something more perfect than what they have…Why do you want to take it away from them, Henry? It’s all they have. A golden chalice of hope.

He believes he is a defender of the people against the moral challenge of a world without absolutes:
I have been in many cities and I have seen the altars upon which they sacrifice the futures of their children to the Gods of Science. And what are their rewards? Confusion and self-destruction. New ways to kill each other in wars. I tell you, going the way of scientists is the way of darkness,

In the wake of the scientists’ contributions to the art of warfare, from gunpowder to atomic bombs, his observation seems justified.  Even Drummond gets this point:

… progress has never been a bargain. You’ve got to pay for it. Sometimes I think there’s a man behind a counter who says, “All right, you can have a telephone; but you’ll have to give up privacy, the charm of distance. Madam, you may vote; but at a price; you lose the right to retreat behind a powder-puff or a petticoat. Mister, you may conquer the air; but the birds will lose their wonder, and the clouds will smell of gasoline!”(Thoughtfully, seeming to look beyond the courtroom) Darwin moved us forward to a hilltop, where we can look back and see the way from which we came. But for this view, this insight, this knowledge, we must abandon our faith in the pleasant poetry of Genesis.

The difference between the two men is that Drummond is willing to pay the price for what he sees as progress and Brady believes the price required for progress is too high.

Brady is at his core a good, but flawed man.  When Reverend Brown, in the throes of zealotry condemns his own daughter, Brady steps up to rein Brown in and console Rachael.  However, he too is prone to zealotry as he shows in the courtroom when he badgers Rachel in attempt to win his case.  This is the point where his passion overcomes his reason and he begins to lose the respect and admiration of his followers.

Brady is also respected by his courtroom adversary.  In the past, he and Drummond had been friends and although now separate, Drummond still respects his old friend, saying after Brady’s death, “There was much greatness in this man.”

But Brady is also a man swollen with pride and supreme self-confidence.  When he learns that the formidable Henry Drummond is to be his adversary in court, he welcomes the challenge.


If the enemy sends its Goliath into battle, it magnifies our cause. Henry Drummond has stalked the courtrooms of this land for forty years. When he fights, headlines follow. (With growing fervor)The whole world will be watching our victory over Drummond. (Dramatically)If St. George had slain a dragonfly, who would remember him.

His pride, as with many tragic heroes, is his fatal flaw.  He is not so much close-minded as he is so sure of the correctness of his position that he cannot recognize the errors in his position.  It is his pride that places him on the stand as an expert witness on the Bible.  At the onset of testimony he is thoroughly self-assured, convinced that Drummond cannot possibly mount an argument sufficient to weaken his beliefs or advance the defense of Bertram Cates, but he underestimates Drummond’s effectiveness.  Drummond pushes and probes at some of the Bible’s inexplicable passages.  He mocks the idea that Jonah was swallowed by “a great fish” and that Joshua caused the sun to stand still in defiance of natural law.  He calls into question the “young Earth theory” of Bishop James Ussher (1581-1656), who calculated from the Bible the precise day of creation:   Sunday 23 October 4004 BC.  Brady uses this theory to refute Drummond’s geological proof that the Earth is millions of years old.  It is at his point that Drummond closes the trap he has laid. 

BRADY:  the Lord began the Creation on the 23rd of October in the Year 4004 B.C. at- uh, at 9 A.M.!
DRUMMOND:  That Eastern Standard Time? (Laughter) Or Rocky Mountain Time? (More laughter) It wasn’t daylight-saving time, was it? Because the Lord didn’t make the sun until the fourth day!
BRADY:  (Fidgeting) That is correct.
DRUMMOND:  (Sharply) The first day. Was it a twenty-four-hour day?
BRADY: The Bible says it was a day.
DRUMMOND:  There wasn’t any sun. How do you know how long it was?
BRADY: (Determined) The Bible says it was a day.
DRUMMOND:  A normal day, a literal day, a twenty-four-hour day? (Pause. BRADY is unsure.)
BRADY: I do not know.
 DRUMMOND: What do you think?
BRADY: (Floundering) I do not think about things that . . . I do not think about!
DRUMMOND:  Do you ever think about things that you do think about? (There is some laughter. But it is dampened by the knowledge and awareness throughout the courtroom, that the trap is about to be sprung) Isn’t it possible that first day was twenty- five hours long? There was no way to measure it, no way to tell! Could it have been twenty-five hours? (Pause. The entire courtroom seems to lean forward.)
BRADY: (Hesitates- then) It is . . . possible. . .(DRUMMOND’S got him. And he knows it! This is the turning point. From here on, the tempo mounts. DRUMMOND is now fully in the driver’s seat. He pounds his questions faster and faster.)
DRUMMOND:  Oh. You interpret that the first day recorded in the Book of Genesis could be of indeterminate length.
BRADY:  (Wriggling) I mean to state that the day referred to is not necessarily a twenty-four-hour day.
DRUMMOND:  It could have been thirty hours! Or a month! Or a year! Or a hundred years! (He brandishes the rock underneath BRADY’S nose) Or ten million years!

Aristotle proposes that “the most powerful elements of emotional interest in Tragedy” are the recognition and reversal of fortune scenes. “Recognition, as the name indicates, is a change from ignorance to knowledge” and is best when “coincident with a Reversal of the Situation.”   In the above exchange, we have Aristotle’s recognition and reversal.  Brady is forced to recognize that the Bible is open to interpretation , that the Biblical “day” of creation may not necessarily be a literal 24 hour day and, if this single point is open to interpretation then the entire canon may be open to interpretation.  Brady’s core belief and that of his followers in the courtroom is shaken and his credibility as defender of the faith has been destroyed.  Herein is the reversal.  Brady has fallen, not only in the eyes of his admirers, but more importantly in his own self-image. For perhaps the first time in his adult life, Brady has been forced to examine his core beliefs and found them wanting.  Instead of standing on firm ground, he has found shifting sand beneath his feet and he has lost his balance.  He is reduced to clinging to his wife, crying in her arms, reduced to a frightened and humiliated child, saying “Mother. They laughed at me, Mother! I can’t stand it when they laugh at me!”  Brady’s subsequent collapse and death in the courtroom the following day is anticlimactic.  His literal death is secondary to the death of his self-image, his supreme self-assurance.  He died on the witness stand, not while trying to deliver a speech no one wants to hear. To add to the tragedy, he is killed by an old friend.

Drummond is the agent of Brady’s destruction and I have to believe that Drummond knew the probable consequences of his actions.  When denied the option of opposing the law prohibiting the teaching of Darwin with expert scientist testimony Drummond is only left with the strategy of personal attack.  In fairness, he is not the first to use the tactic.  Brady, in attacking Cates through the testimony of Rachel Brown has already set the precedent.  Ultimately the attack on Cates really doesn’t matter; Cates motive really doesn’t matter.  Brady attacks Cates because he is personally offended by what Cates has done and must show Cates up as actively antagonistic to religion and not simply a supporter of intellectual freedom.  In other words, Brady must create a bogeyman that he can subsequently defeat.

Following his example, Drummond, unable to defend Cates’ crime unless he can undermine the legitimacy of the law, has been thwarted by the court.  The only road open to him is to show that the guiding force behind the law, the literal interpretation of Genesis, is vulnerable to questioning even by the faithful and that any law that prohibits question is unjust.  He chooses Brady as the symbol of literalism and Drummond undermines literalism by destroying its symbol.  Brady could have refused to testify, but his pride compels him to do so.  If he had refused to testify, the trial’s outcome would not have been altered in the least. Cates would have been found guilty and Drummond would have filed his appeal.  Was it really necessary for Drummond to destroy Brady?

In tragedy, we expect a certain inevitability, a certain sense that the events could only unfold as they do.   Drummond must attack close-mindedness wherever he finds it.  While he certainly knows the attack on Brady and the faithful will not impact the court’s verdict, he feels compelled to use the forum of the courtroom to advance the principle of intellectual freedom against its’ suppression by unthinking religious faith.  His passion for his cause is no less fanatical than Brady’s.  His quest is to advance his cause and ultimately, consequence, personal and societal, be damned.

Brady, as we already discussed, is obsessed with consequences.  He sees unrestricted scientific progress and knowledge as potentially destructive.  He believes that unrestricted knowledge threatens man’s morals by weakening his faith in God and moral absolutes.  Tragically and ironically, he lacks sufficient faith in the power of his religion to overcome intellectual attacks.  He fears “the simple people” will degenerate morally if their faith in the literal word of God as contained in the Bible is called to question.   He must take the stand and answers Drummond’s questions because he believes only he is able to stand firm in his faith against the attacks of this “  agent of darkness.”  Tragically, he is wrong.  It falls to Drummond to play St. George against Brady’s dragon.   

After Brady’s defeat and subsequent death, Drummond seems overcome by a sense of sadness, but not regret. His reaction is like that of a man who has to put down a good and faithful dog who has grown dangerous.  He is sad to be the agent of its’ death, but he recognizes that it must be done for the greater good.  So it is with Drummond who sees in Brady a great man, but one who, because of his greatness, can impede the progress of man.  Such a man must ultimately be removed for Drummond’s vision of the greater good.

1.      Bywater, Imgram. With a preface by Gilbert Murray. Aristotle on the Art of Poetry. New York: Oxford University Press, 1920.
2.      Fyfe, Hamilton W. Aristotle's Art of Poetry. London: Oxford at the Clarendon Press, 1940.
3.       Hardison Jr., O. B. Aristotle's Poetics. Translation by Leon Golden. Tallahassee, Florida: University Presses of Florida, 1981.

No comments:

Post a Comment